影音先锋男人资源在线观看,精品国产日韩亚洲一区91,中文字幕日韩国产,2018av男人天堂,青青伊人精品,久久久久久久综合日本亚洲,国产日韩欧美一区二区三区在线

“Museum and mausoleum are connectedmore than phonetic ...

上傳人:1666****666 文檔編號(hào):37600074 上傳時(shí)間:2021-11-03 格式:DOC 頁(yè)數(shù):10 大?。?7.01KB
收藏 版權(quán)申訴 舉報(bào) 下載
“Museum and mausoleum are connectedmore than phonetic ..._第1頁(yè)
第1頁(yè) / 共10頁(yè)
“Museum and mausoleum are connectedmore than phonetic ..._第2頁(yè)
第2頁(yè) / 共10頁(yè)
“Museum and mausoleum are connectedmore than phonetic ..._第3頁(yè)
第3頁(yè) / 共10頁(yè)

下載文檔到電腦,查找使用更方便

15 積分

下載資源

還剩頁(yè)未讀,繼續(xù)閱讀

資源描述:

《“Museum and mausoleum are connectedmore than phonetic ...》由會(huì)員分享,可在線閱讀,更多相關(guān)《“Museum and mausoleum are connectedmore than phonetic ...(10頁(yè)珍藏版)》請(qǐng)?jiān)谘b配圖網(wǎng)上搜索。

1、10 Spaces of life and death: the museum and the laboratory Beth Lord, University of Dundee, b.lord@dundee.ac.uk DRAFT CONFERENCE PAPER. DO NOT PUBLISH OR CITE WITHOUT AUTHOR’S PERMISSION. In his essay “Valery Proust Museum”, Theodor Adorno discusses the museum in terms of the life and d

2、eath of artworks. “The German word museal has unpleasant overtones. It describes objects to which the observer no longer has a vital relationship and which are in the process of dying. … Museum and mausoleum are connected by more than phonetic association. Museums are like the family sepulchres

3、of works of art.” This forms part of a broad tendency of modernist philosophers to connect museums with death. “However high their quality and power of impression, however good their state of preservation, however certain their interpretation, placing [artworks] in a collection has withdrawn t

4、hem from their own world.” (Heidegger, “The Origin of the Work of Art”) The museum “detaches all art from its connections with life and the particular conditions of our approach to it.” (Gadamer, Truth and Method) “We occasionally sense that these works were not after all intended to end up be

5、tween these morose walls, for the pleasure of Sunday strollers or Monday ‘intellectuals’. We are aware that something has been lost and that this meditative necropolis is not the true milieu of art – that so many joys and sorrows, so much anger, and so many labours were not destined one day to refle

6、ct the museum’s mournful light. … The museum kills the vehemence of painting… It is the historicity of death.” (Merleau-Ponty, “Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence”) Perhaps the root of all this is Hegel’s remark that “art, considered in its highest vocation, is and remains for us a thing

7、 of the past. Thereby it has lost for us genuine truth and life, and has rather been transferred into our ideas instead of maintaining its earlier necessity in reality and occupying its higher place” (11). Hegel mourns the dissociation of art from the spiritual world of the church or the Greek templ

8、e, and notes that art has “now” become intellectualized, has become a matter of criticism, judgment and thought. The need for a philosophy of art comes about most urgently under these circumstances. We find the same sense of mourning that art has become detached from the spiritual realm (togethe

9、r with the urgency of raising anew the question of art) in Heidegger and Gadamer. Because the museum replaces the church or temple as the dwelling place for works of art, all these thinkers associate the museum with the work of art’s detachment from its living environment. The idea that art has

10、its original “l(fā)ife” in a certain milieu (e.g. a church, a chapel, an aristocratic home) is problematic for a number of reasons. If art dies when removed from its original environment, then it has life and power only because of its architectural or spiritual setting. It is strange to attribute “l(fā)ife”

11、 to these extrinsic factors, rather than to the power immanent within the work itself. It speaks against its autonomy. Arguably museums give artworks more autonomy than they had in the church; given Adorno’s conviction that the autonomy of art is what is most important, it is strange that he would s

12、uggest that the life or death of the artwork depends on its location. Adorno suggests that museums “kill” artworks when they take them out of their original surroundings and bring them together without context. Whether we put artworks in museums or in reconstructed churches or stately homes, they lo

13、se their autonomy, their vitality and power. The autonomy of the artwork cannot be very strong if it is so easily negated by its physical situation. Adorno (and Hegel) recognize the impossibility of the artwork’s return to its original home. Given that there are no longer any “original settings”

14、for artworks, given that art is no longer created to be housed in churches, temples, or mansions – in other words, given Hegel’s dictum that art in that sense is a thing of the past, what do we do with art? Adorno looks at the writings of Valery and Proust on museums to answer this question. Val

15、ery writes of the museum in terms of death, disorder, and constraint (Adorno 176-7). He speaks of the “authoritarian gesture” that takes away his cane and his pipe when he enters the museum. He finds chaos in the ordering of the sculptures. What he objects to most is being asked to look at so many w

16、orks of art simultaneously, since a beautiful work of art is so distinct that it “kills the ones around it”. The paintings, brought together in one space, must kill one another. “Dead visions are entombed” in the museum. The museum is where “we put the art of the past to death”. But Valery also writ

17、es about the “sacred awe” that fills the museum, the reverential tones in which people speak. The overall image is not just of where artworks come to die, but where they are brought to be sacrificed. Finally Valery concludes that this situation has come about through the detachment of artworks from

18、their original settings. He says of artworks “Their mother is dead, their mother, architecture. While she lived, she gave them their place, their definition. … While she was alive, they knew what they wanted.” Valery suggests that the sacred space of the church, the architectural “mother” that gives

19、 life to artworks, has been replaced with a different kind of sacred space in the museum, a space of violence and sacrifice which remains as a monumental sepulchre. Proust, by contrast, is positive about the museum, and speaks of it in terms of life rather than death. The chaos that Valery compla

20、ined of is, for Proust, to be celebrated, the multiplicity of paintings connected by flows of memory and consciousness. The spareness of the museum, its display of paintings free of context, is essential for consciousness to find a way in to the painting. Proust speaks against the tendency to displa

21、y artworks in contextual settings or in homes. “The masterpiece observed during dinner no longer produces in us the exhilarating happiness that can be had only in a museum, where the rooms, in their sober abstinence from all decorative detail, symbolize the inner spaces into which the artist withdra

22、ws to create the work.” (Adorno 179) The museum for Proust is the very mind of the artist, where not the death but the birth of artworks takes place. Briefly, Valery champions the autonomy of the artwork, its objective character and immanent coherence, over against the contingency of the subject

23、. Proust by contrast rejects fixed truths and gives primacy to the flux of experience and memory. Adorno suggests that neither Valery nor Proust is “right” about art. There must be a dialectic between their positions, where one passes over into the other (183): Valery can only become aware of the au

24、tonomy of the artwork through Proustian self-reflection in the museum. Concomitantly, works of art must be sent to their death in order to live. The museum is necessary to achieve this dialectic in art. “Works of art can fully embody the promesse du bonheur only when they have been uprooted fro

25、m their native soil and have set out along the path to their own destruction. … The procedure which today relegates every work of art to the museum … is irreversible. It is not solely reprehensible, however, for it presages a situation in which art, having completed its estrangement from human ends

26、, returns … to life.” (Adorno 185) The museum kills art and thereby provides the conditions for its rebirth and life. The museum, for Adorno, is a space of death and necessarily so; a space for the transition from life to death and back to life again, thus continuing in the tradition of the churc

27、h, the temple, the site of sacrifice. This cycle of death, rebirth, and life we find repeated again and again in Oteiza’s writings – about artworks and about his own role as artist. When he states, in his “Experimental Proposal” accompanying the Sao Paolo Biennal of 1957, “I return from Death. Wh

28、at we tried to bury grows here” (qtd by Zulaika, 11), he suggests the artist’s own return from metaphorical “death” to life (47). But he also repeats the dialectic that Adorno sets up. The Biennal, even more than the museum, is surely to be seen as the site of the death of artworks: the ultimate dec

29、ontextualized and desacralized space. The work of art dies and is buried in such a space, but thereby somehow regains its life. What we tried to bury – the artwork that died in the museum – grows here, in the museum, nevertheless. How does the life of the artwork emerge from its burial – and how

30、is the artwork reborn in the same space in which it died? Perhaps a clue can be found in Oteiza’s search for an aesthetic “resolution of death” (qtd by Zulaika, 15). The artwork is a “solution” to the problem of death that supplants the religious solution: the notion of an afterlife. The artwork is

31、posited in place of the afterlife, as concretized in Oteiza’s series of funeral stelas. The job of the artwork is to live beyond its death, to cheat death. Art is “the dominion over death granted to mankind” (Zulaika, 18). For this reason, the threat of the death of the artwork in the museum is the

32、greatest danger. Perhaps it is to this danger that we must attribute Oteiza’s suspicion of museums: the museum will kill the artwork and prevent it fulfilling its function to cheat death. Yet its function can only come about after death, through which it achieves its afterlife. The museum is therefo

33、re both the greatest threat and the supreme opportunity for art: the opportunity for it to live in spite of its death. The artwork has life before it enters the museum, but a life that has not yet been strengthened or made enduring through its dialectic with death. The enduring living of the artwork

34、 exists only through the dialectic of life and death, and this dialectic occurs only in the museum, as Adorno indicates. It is in this context that I think we should approach Oteiza’s “Experimental laboratories”. Oteiza began to create these experimental laboratories in the early 1950s, and used

35、them in preparation for the Sao Paolo Biennal. Using materials such as chalk, paper, and tin, Oteiza created objects exploring certain problems, shapes, spatial configurations and movements. He classified these objects into “experimental family groups” on shelves reminiscent of the scientific labora

36、tory or the pharmacist’s storeroom. The objects were in some cases used as maquettes or models for larger sculptures, so the laboratories can be seen as collections of models for future use. Margit Rowell refers to the laboratory project as a “vast repertory of tiny maquettes”, whose principal purpo

37、se was to aid the artist in his unique working methods: “[Oteiza’s] point of departure would be a basic visual or mathematical concept which he would interpret in every conceivable variation until the exhaustion of the given theme. This undertaking would create large ‘families’ of motifs, from wh

38、ich he would select those he found the most successful, and realize them as full-scale sculptures in stone or metal. This ‘experiemental laboratory’ represented a source of plastic solutions from which he would draw thoroughtout his working life.” (Rowell, 346) Clearly Oteiza did use the laborato

39、ry objects as models, and the laboratories as resources for sculptural experimentation. However, this interpretation of the laboratories as repositories of models seems to me to overlook two important things. First, the extent to which the laboratories are themselves works of art, as evinced by the

40、installation of entire laboratories in, e.g., the Venice Biennale of 1988 (whole laboratories behind glass). The laboratory is not just a collection of maquettes, but is itself presented as a sculpture. Second, the way in which the laboratories, in their presentation and classification of objects, r

41、ecall early museum displays, particularly those of the 18th century. In those displays, natural and cultural objects are displayed together, grouped according to visual similarities in shape, colour, or size. Oteiza’s objects are grouped together in ways that are typical of early museum displays: on

42、e shelf is full of objects made of wire; another is full of objects that are deconstructed circles, another is full of objects seemingly connected only by the fact that they are roughly the same size. We see the same kinds of classification decisions informing Enlightenment museum displays: grouping

43、s are based on the look of objects and what they visually have in common, rather than dividing them along scientific, cultural, chronological, or disciplinary lines. It’s significant, I think, that Oteiza presents his laboratories as museum displays. He creates artefacts which are then to be pres

44、ented in museum displays, and that whole display is to be presented as a work of art and itself placed within a museum. The museum is the space in which the original life of the artwork enters into a dialectic with its death, resulting in its afterlife, its enduring living. Oteiza creates the space

45、in which this dialectic is to occur; effectively, he creates museums for his artworks to live in. Oteiza, then, creates the setting for the death of his own work by creating museum displays; and in creating the objects that populate these displays, he creates objects to be sacrificed within these di

46、splays, to die and then be reborn. In other words, the laboratories represent neither the life nor the death of artworks, but rather the dialectical structure of their process of living. They live – have energy and movement – only through fulfilling their function of cheating or mastering death.

47、 But that afterlife comes about only through their death in the museum. Oteiza creates not only the works, but the conditions under which the works can live. The word laboratory evokes ongoing process and experiment. The work of the laboratory is to produce the ongoing living of artworks, their life

48、 after death. After all, Oteiza’s own museum project, the Cube, was proposed to be an experimental centre (Zulaika 63-4): a laboratory on a grand scale, a museum that would “kill” its contents in order to give them a place to live. References Adorno, T. W. “Valery Proust Museum”, Prism

49、s, trans. S. and S. Weber. MIT Press, 1983. Gadamer, H.-G. Truth and Method, trans. J. Weinsheimer and D.G. Marshall. London: Continuum, 2004. Hegel, G.W.F. Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, trans. T.M. Knox. 2 vols. Oxford: OUP, 1998. Heidegger, M. “The Origin of the Work of Art”, Poetry Languag

50、e Thought, trans. A. Hofstadter. New York: Harper & Row, 1975. Merleau-Ponty, M. “Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence”, The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader, ed. G.A. Johnson, trans. M.B. Smith. Evanston: Northwestern UP, 1993. Rowell, M. “A sense of place/a sense of space: the sculpture of Jorge Oteiza”, in Oteiza: Mito y Modernidad/Mitoa eta Modernotasuna. Bilbao: Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa, 2004. Zulaika, J. “Introduction: Oteiza’s Return from the Future”. In J. Oteiza, Oteiza’s Selected Writings, ed. J. Zulaika, trans. F. Fornoff. Reno: University of Nevada Press, 2003.

展開(kāi)閱讀全文
溫馨提示:
1: 本站所有資源如無(wú)特殊說(shuō)明,都需要本地電腦安裝OFFICE2007和PDF閱讀器。圖紙軟件為CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.壓縮文件請(qǐng)下載最新的WinRAR軟件解壓。
2: 本站的文檔不包含任何第三方提供的附件圖紙等,如果需要附件,請(qǐng)聯(lián)系上傳者。文件的所有權(quán)益歸上傳用戶所有。
3.本站RAR壓縮包中若帶圖紙,網(wǎng)頁(yè)內(nèi)容里面會(huì)有圖紙預(yù)覽,若沒(méi)有圖紙預(yù)覽就沒(méi)有圖紙。
4. 未經(jīng)權(quán)益所有人同意不得將文件中的內(nèi)容挪作商業(yè)或盈利用途。
5. 裝配圖網(wǎng)僅提供信息存儲(chǔ)空間,僅對(duì)用戶上傳內(nèi)容的表現(xiàn)方式做保護(hù)處理,對(duì)用戶上傳分享的文檔內(nèi)容本身不做任何修改或編輯,并不能對(duì)任何下載內(nèi)容負(fù)責(zé)。
6. 下載文件中如有侵權(quán)或不適當(dāng)內(nèi)容,請(qǐng)與我們聯(lián)系,我們立即糾正。
7. 本站不保證下載資源的準(zhǔn)確性、安全性和完整性, 同時(shí)也不承擔(dān)用戶因使用這些下載資源對(duì)自己和他人造成任何形式的傷害或損失。

相關(guān)資源

更多
正為您匹配相似的精品文檔
關(guān)于我們 - 網(wǎng)站聲明 - 網(wǎng)站地圖 - 資源地圖 - 友情鏈接 - 網(wǎng)站客服 - 聯(lián)系我們

copyright@ 2023-2025  zhuangpeitu.com 裝配圖網(wǎng)版權(quán)所有   聯(lián)系電話:18123376007

備案號(hào):ICP2024067431號(hào)-1 川公網(wǎng)安備51140202000466號(hào)


本站為文檔C2C交易模式,即用戶上傳的文檔直接被用戶下載,本站只是中間服務(wù)平臺(tái),本站所有文檔下載所得的收益歸上傳人(含作者)所有。裝配圖網(wǎng)僅提供信息存儲(chǔ)空間,僅對(duì)用戶上傳內(nèi)容的表現(xiàn)方式做保護(hù)處理,對(duì)上載內(nèi)容本身不做任何修改或編輯。若文檔所含內(nèi)容侵犯了您的版權(quán)或隱私,請(qǐng)立即通知裝配圖網(wǎng),我們立即給予刪除!